fiction.wikisort.org - Writer

Search / Calendar

Paul Nicolai Hartmann (German: [ˈhaʁtman]; 20 February 1882 – 9 October 1950) was a Baltic German philosopher. He is regarded as a key representative of critical realism[3] and as one of the most important twentieth-century metaphysicians.

Nicolai Hartmann
Born19 February [O.S. 7] 1882
Riga, Livonia Governorate, Russian Empire
Died9 October 1950(1950-10-09) (aged 68)
Göttingen, Landkreis Göttingen, Lower Saxony, West Germany
Alma materUniversity of Yuryev
Saint Petersburg Imperial University
University of Marburg
Era20th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolContinental philosophy
Neo-Kantianism (early)
Realist phenomenology (late)
Critical realism (late)
Academic advisorsHermann Cohen
Paul Natorp
Doctoral studentsCarl Gustav Hempel
Main interests
Metaphysics, epistemology, ethics
Notable ideas
Strata of Being (Seinsschichten),[1] new ontology (neue Ontologie),[2] categorial novum
Influences

Biography


Hartmann was born a Baltic German in Riga, which was then the capital of the Governorate of Livonia in the Russian Empire, and which is now in Latvia. He was the son of the engineer Carl August Hartmann and his wife Helene, born Hackmann. He attended from 1897 the German-language high school in Saint Petersburg. In the years 1902–1903 he studied Medicine at the University of Yuryev (now Tartu), and 1903–1905 classical philology and philosophy at the Saint Petersburg Imperial University with his friend Vasily Sesemann. In 1905 he went to the University of Marburg, where he studied with the neo-Kantians Hermann Cohen and Paul Natorp. In Marburg began a lifelong friendship with Heinz Heimsoeth. In 1907 he received his doctorate with the thesis Das Seinsproblem in der griechischen Philosophie vor Plato (The Problem of Being in Greek Philosophy Before Plato). In 1909 he published the book Platos Logik des Seins (The Logic of Being in Plato). The same year he completed his habilitation on Proclus: Des Proklus Diadochus philosophische Anfangsgründe der Mathematik (Proclus Diadochus' Philosophical Elements of Mathematics).

In 1911, Hartmann married Alice Stepanitz, with whom he had a daughter, Dagmar, in 1912. In 1912 he published Die philosophischen Grundfragen der Biologie (The Philosophical Foundations of Biology). From 1914 to 1918 he did military service as an interpreter, letter censor, and intelligence officer. In 1919, i.e., after the war, he received a position as Privatdozent in Marburg. Around this time he met Martin Heidegger. In 1920 he became Associate Professor (außerordentlicher Professor) and in 1921 appeared the work that established him as an independent philosophical thinker, Grundzüge einer Metaphysik der Erkenntnis (Foundation of a Metaphysics of Knowledge). The following year he became Full Professor (ordentlicher Professor) as successor of the Chair held by Natorp. In 1925, he moved to Cologne, where he came into contact with Max Scheler. In 1926 he published his second major work—Ethik—in which he develops a material value ethics akin to that of Scheler. The same year he divorced from his wife.

In 1929 Hartmann married Frida Rosenfeld, with whom he had a son, Olaf (1930), and a daughter, Lise (1932). In 1931 he became Professor of Theoretical Philosophy in Berlin. He held the Chair until 1945. During this time he successively published many pieces of his ontology: Das Problem des geistigen Seins (The Problem of Spiritual Being) (1933), Zur Grundlegung der Ontologie (On the Foundation of Ontology) (1935), Möglichkeit und Wirklichkeit (Possibility and Actuality) (1938) and Der Aufbau der realen Welt. Grundriß der allgemeinen Kategorienlehre (The Structure of the Real World. Outline of the General Theory of Categories) (1940). The unrest of the National Socialist period seems to have left Hartmann relatively undisturbed in his task of developing a new ontology. In the "'-Dossiers über Philosophie-Professoren" (i.e. SD-files concerning philosophy professors) that were set up by the SS Security Service (SD) Nicolai Hartmann was classified from an SS-point of view in the following way: "has always been a nationalist. Loyal to National Socialism, too, without political activity, but a social attitude has to be acknowledged. (cf. donations to the NSV and hosting children during school vacations)".[4]

In 1942, Hartmann edited a volume entitled Systematische Philosophie, in which he contributed the essay Neue Wege der Ontologie (New Ways of Ontology), which summarizes his work in ontology.

Between 1945 and 1950, Hartmann taught in Göttingen. He died of a stroke in 1950. In the year of his death, there appeared his Philosophie der Natur (Philosophy of Nature). His works Teleologisches Denken (Teleological Thinking) (1951) and Ästhetik (Aesthetics) (1953) were published posthumously.

He is regarded as an important representative of critical realism and as one of the major metaphysicians of the twentieth century. Among Hartmann's many students were Boris Pasternak, Hans-Georg Gadamer, Emil Cioran, Jakob Klein, Delfim Santos and Max Wehrli. He is the modern discoverer of emergence — originally called by him categorial novum. His encyclopedic work is basically forgotten today, although famous during his lifetime. His early work in the philosophy of biology has been cited in modern discussions of genomics and cloning, and his views on consciousness and free will are currently in vogue among contributors to the Journal of Consciousness Studies.


Ontology


Nicolai Hartmann equates ontology with Aristotle's science of being qua being.[5][6] This science involves studying the most general characteristics of entities, usually referred to as categories, and the relations between them.[7] According to Hartmann, the most general categories are:

  1. Moments of being (Seinsmomente): existence (Dasein) and essence (Sosein)
  2. Modes of being (Seinsweisen): reality and ideality
  3. Modalities of being (Seinsmodi): possibility, actuality and necessity

Existence and essence


The existence of an entity constitutes the fact that this entity is there, that it exists. Essence, on the other hand, constitutes what this entity is like, what its characteristics are. Every entity has both of these modes of being.[8] But, as Hartmann points out, there is no absolute difference between existence and essence. For example, the existence of a leaf belongs to the essence of the tree while the existence of the tree belongs to the essence of the forest.[9]


Reality and ideality


Reality and ideality are two disjunctive categories: every entity is either real or ideal. Ideal entities are universal, returnable and always existing while real entities are individual, unique and destructible.[10] Among the ideal entities are mathematical objects and values.[11] Reality is made up of a chain of temporal events. Reality is obtrusive, it is often experienced as a form of resistance in contrast to ideality.


Modalities of being


The modalities of being are divided into the absolute modalities (actuality and non-actuality) and the relative modalities (possibility, impossibility and necessity). The relative modalities are relative in the sense that they depend on the absolute modalities: something is possible, impossible or necessary because something else is actual. Hartmann analyzes modality in the real sphere in terms of necessary conditions.[10] An entity becomes actual if all its necessary conditions obtain. If all these factors obtain, it is necessary that the entity exists. But as long as one of its factors is missing, it can't become actual, it is impossible. This has the consequence that all positive and all the negative modalities fall together: whatever is possible is both actual and necessary, whatever is not necessary is both non-actual and impossible.[9] This is true also in the ideal sphere, where possibility is given by being free from contradictions.


Levels of reality


In Hartmann's ontological theory, the levels of reality are: (1) the inorganic level (German: anorganische Schicht), (2) the organic level (organische Schicht), (3) the psychical/emotional level (seelische Schicht) and (4) the intellectual/cultural level (geistige Schicht).[12] In The Structure of the Real World (Der Aufbau der realen Welt), Hartmann postulates four laws that apply to the levels of reality.

  1. The law of recurrence: Lower categories recur in the higher levels as a subaspect of higher categories, but never vice versa.
  2. The law of modification: The categorial elements modify in their recurrence in the higher levels (they are shaped by the characteristics of the higher levels).
  3. The law of the novum: The higher category is composed of a diversity of lower elements, but it is a specific novum that is not included in the lower levels.
  4. The law of distance between levels: Since the different levels do not develop continuously but in leaps, they can be clearly distinguished.

Ethical theory


The central concept of Hartmann's ethical theory is that of a value. Hartmann's 1926 book, Ethik, elaborates a material ethics of value according to which moral knowledge is achieved through phenomenological investigation into our experiences of values. Moral phenomena are understood by Hartmann to be experiences of a realm of being which is distinct from that of material things, namely, the realm of values. The values inhabiting this realm are unchanging, super-temporal, and super-historical, though human consciousness of them shifts in focus over time. Borrowing a style of phrase from Kant, Hartmann characterizes values as conditions of the possibility of goods; in other words, values are what make it possible for situations in the world to be good. Our knowledge of the goodness (or badness) of situations is derived from our emotional experiences of them, experiences which are made possible by an a priori capacity for the appreciation of value. For Hartmann, this means that our awareness of the value of a state of affairs is not arrived at through a process of reasoning, but rather, by way of an experience of feeling, which he calls valuational consciousness. If, then, ethics is the study of what one ought to do, or what states of affairs one ought to bring about, such studies, according to Hartmann, must be carried out by paying close attention to our emotional capacities to discern what is valuable in the world. As such, Hartmann's conception of proper moral philosophy contrasts with rationalist and formalist theories, such as Kant's, according to which ethical knowledge is derived from purely rational principles.


Quotations


"The tragedy of man is that of somebody who is starving and sitting at a richly laden table but does not reach out with his hand, because he cannot see what is right in front of him. For the real world has inexhaustible splendour, the real life is full of meaning and abundance, where we grasp it, it is full of miracles and glory."[13]


Works



Works in German


Books
Articles

Translations in English



See also



References


  1. Agazzi Evandro, Montecucco Luisa (eds.), Complexity And Emergence, World Scientific, 2002, p. 189.
  2. Nicolai Hartmann, Studien zur Neuen Ontologie und Anthropologie, Walter de Gruyter, 2014, p. 265.
  3. Herbert Schnädelbach, Philosophy in Germany 1831-1933, Cambridge UP, 1984, p. 209.
  4. Georg Leaman, Gerd Simon: Deutsche Philosophen aus der Sicht des Sicherheitsdienstes des Reichsführers SS. Jahrbuch für Soziologie-Geschichte 1992, pages 261-292. Original SD-file text: "von jeher national. Loyal auch gegenüber dem NS, ohne pol. Aktivität, aber durchaus sozial eingestellt. (Siehe Zuwendung für die NSV, Aufnahme von Ferienkindern usw.)"
  5. Hartmann, Nicolai (1935). "1. Kapitel. Die ontologische Grundfrage". Zur Grundlegung der Ontologie. W. De Gruyter.
  6. Aristotle; Reeve, C. D. C. (11 February 2016). "Book Epsilon". Metaphysics. Hackett Publishing. ISBN 978-1-62466-441-0.
  7. Spiegelberg, Herbert (1963). The Phenomenological Movement a Historical Introduction (3rd ed.). M. Nijhoff. pp. 309–310.
  8. Hartmann, Nicolai (1935). "12. Kapitel. Die Trennung von Dasein und Sosein". Zur Grundlegung der Ontologie. W. De Gruyter.
  9. Bochenski, Joseph M. (1974). "22. Nicolai Hartmann". Contemporary European Philosophy. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-00133-6.
  10. Cicovacki, Predrag (2014). "I.3 Modifications of Being". The Analysis of Wonder: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Nicolai Hartmann. Bloomsbury Publishing USA. ISBN 978-1-62356-974-7.
  11. Mohanty, J. N. (1997). "Chapter 3: Nicolai Hartmann's Phenomenological Ontology". Phenomenology. Between Essentialism and Transcendental Philosophy. Northwestern University Press.
  12. Poli, Roberto (2017). "Nicolai Hartmann". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  13. Nicolai Hartmann: Ethik. 4. Aufl., de Gruyter, Berlin 1962, p. 11. Original in German: "Die Tragik des Menschen ist die des Verhungernden, der an der gedeckten Tafel sitzt und die Hand nicht ausstreckt, weil er nicht sieht, was vor ihm ist. Denn die wirkliche Welt ist unerschöpflich an Fülle, das wirkliche Leben ist wertgetränkt und überströmend, und wo wir es fassen, da ist es voller Wunder und Herrlichkeit."

Further reading


Books
Articles





Текст в блоке "Читать" взят с сайта "Википедия" и доступен по лицензии Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike; в отдельных случаях могут действовать дополнительные условия.

Другой контент может иметь иную лицензию. Перед использованием материалов сайта WikiSort.org внимательно изучите правила лицензирования конкретных элементов наполнения сайта.

2019-2024
WikiSort.org - проект по пересортировке и дополнению контента Википедии