fiction.wikisort.org - Writer

Search / Calendar

Robin George Collingwood FBA (/ˈkɒlɪŋwʊd/; 22 February 1889 – 9 January 1943) was an English philosopher, historian and archaeologist. He is best known for his philosophical works, including The Principles of Art (1938) and the posthumously published The Idea of History (1946).

R. G. Collingwood

FBA
Born
Robin George Collingwood

22 February 1889
Gillhead, Cartmel Fell, Lancashire, England
Died9 January 1943(1943-01-09) (aged 53)
Coniston, Lancashire, England
Alma materUniversity College, Oxford
Notable workThe Principles of Art (1938)
The Idea of History (1946)
Era20th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolBritish idealism
Historism[1]
InstitutionsPembroke College, Oxford
Main interests
Metaphysics
Philosophy of history
Aesthetics
Notable ideas
Historical imagination
Coining the English term historicism[1][2]
Aesthetic expressivism
Influences
Influenced
    • Alasdair MacIntyre
    • Niall Ferguson
    • Leo Strauss
    • Quentin Skinner

Biography


Collingwood was born 22 February 1889 in Cartmel, Grange-over-Sands, then in Lancashire, the son of the artist and archaeologist W. G. Collingwood, who acted as John Ruskin's private secretary in the final years of Ruskin's life. Collingwood's mother was also an artist and a talented pianist. He was educated at Rugby School and University College, Oxford, where he gained a First in Classical Moderations (Greek and Latin) in 1910 and a congratulatory First in Greats (Ancient History and Philosophy) in 1912.[4] Prior to graduation he was elected a fellow of Pembroke College, Oxford.

Collingwood was a fellow of Pembroke College, Oxford, for some 15 years until becoming the Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy at Magdalen College, Oxford. He was taught by the historian and archaeologist F. J. Haverfield, at the time Camden Professor of Ancient History. Important influences on Collingwood were the Italian Idealists Benedetto Croce, Giovanni Gentile and Guido de Ruggiero, the last of whom was also a close friend. Other important influences were Hegel, Kant, Giambattista Vico, F. H. Bradley and J. A. Smith.

After several years of increasingly debilitating strokes Collingwood died at Coniston, Lancashire, on 9 January 1943. He was a practising Anglican throughout his life.


Philosopher



Philosophy of history


Collingwood is widely noted for The Idea of History (1946), which was collated from various sources soon after his death by a student, T. M. Knox. It came to be a major inspiration for philosophy of history in the English-speaking world and is extensively cited, leading to an ironic remark by commentator Louis Mink that Collingwood is coming to be "the best known neglected thinker of our time".[5]

Collingwood categorized history as a science, defining a science as "any organized body of knowledge."[6] However, he distinguished history from natural sciences because the concerns of these two branches are different: natural sciences are concerned with the physical world while history, in its most common usage, is concerned with social sciences and human affairs.[7] Collingwood pointed out a fundamental difference between knowing things in the present (or in the natural sciences) and knowing history. To come to know things in the present or about things in the natural sciences, "real" things can be observed, as they are in existence or that have substance right now.

Since the internal thought processes of historical persons cannot be perceived with the physical senses and past historical events cannot be directly observed, history must be methodologically different from natural sciences. History, being a study of the human mind, is interested in the thoughts and motivations of the actors in history, this insight being encapsulated in his epigram “All history is the history of thought.”[8] Therefore, Collingwood suggested that a historian must "reconstruct" history by using "historical imagination" to "re-enact" the thought processes of historical persons based on information and evidence from historical sources. Re-enactment of thought refers to the idea that the historian can access not only a thought process similar to that of the historical actor, but the actual thought process itself. Consider Collingwood's words regarding the study of Plato:

In its immediacy, as an actual experience of his own, Plato's argument must undoubtedly have grown up out of a discussion of some sort, though I do not know what it was, and been closely connected with such a discussion. Yet if I not only read his argument but understand it, follow it in my own mind by re-arguing it with and for myself, the process of argument which I go through is not a process resembling Plato's, it actually is Plato's, so far as I understand him rightly.[9]

In Collingwood's understanding, a thought is a single entity accessible to the public and therefore, regardless of how many people have the same thought, it is still a singular thought. "Thoughts, in other words, are to be distinguished on the basis of purely qualitative criteria, and if there are two people entertaining the (qualitatively) same thought, there is (numerically) only one thought since there is only one propositional content."[10] Therefore, if historians follow the correct line of inquiry in response to a historical source and reason correctly, they can arrive at the same thought the author of their source had and, in so doing, "re-enact" that thought.

Collingwood rejected what he deemed "scissors-and-paste history" in which the historian rejects a statement recorded by their subject either because it contradicts another historical statement or because it contradicts the historian's own understanding of the world. As he states in Principles of History, sometimes a historian will encounter "a story which he simply cannot believe, a story characteristic, perhaps, of the superstitions or prejudices of the author's time or the circle in which he lived, but not credible to a more enlightened age, and therefore to be omitted."[11] This, Collingwood argues, is an unacceptable way to do history. Sources which make claims that do not align with current understandings of the world were still created by rational humans who had reason for creating them. Therefore, these sources are valuable and ought to be investigated further in order to get at the historical context in which they were created and for what reason.


Philosophy of art


The Principles of Art (1938) comprises Collingwood's most developed treatment of aesthetic questions. Collingwood held (following Benedetto Croce) that works of art are essentially expressions of emotion. For Collingwood, an important social role for artists is to clarify and articulate emotions from their community.

Collingwood developed a position later known as aesthetic expressivism (not to be confused with various other views typically called expressivism), a thesis first developed by Croce.[12]


Political philosophy


In politics Collingwood defended the ideals of what he called liberalism "in its Continental sense":

The essence of this conception is ... the idea of a community as governing itself by fostering the free expression of all political opinions that take shape within it, and finding some means of reducing this multiplicity of opinions to a unity.[13]

In his Autobiography, Collingwood confessed that his politics had always been "democratic" and "liberal", and shared Guido de Ruggiero's opinion that socialism had rendered a great service to liberalism by pointing out the shortcomings of laissez-faire economics.[14]


Archaeologist


Collingwood was not just a philosopher of history but also a practising historian and archaeologist. He was, during his time, a leading authority on Roman Britain: he spent his term time at Oxford teaching philosophy but devoted his long vacations to archaeology.

He began work along Hadrian's Wall. The family home was at Coniston in the Lake District and his father was a leading figure in the Cumberland and Westmorland Archaeological Society. Collingwood was drawn in on a number of excavations and put forward the theory that Hadrian's Wall was not so much a fighting platform but an elevated sentry walk.[15] He also put forward the suggestion that Hadrian's defensive system also included a number of forts along the Cumberland coast.

He was very active in the 1930 Wall Pilgrimage for which he prepared the ninth edition of Bruce's Handbook.

His final and most controversial excavation in Cumbria was that of a circular ring ditch near Penrith known as King Arthur's Round Table in 1937. It appeared to be a Neolithic henge monument, and Collingwood's excavations, failing to find conclusive evidence of Neolithic activity, nevertheless found the base of two stone pillars, a possible cremation trench and some post holes. Sadly, his subsequent ill health prevented him undertaking a second season so the work was handed over to the German prehistorian Gerhard Bersu, who queried some of Collingwood's findings. However, recently, Grace Simpson, the daughter of the excavator F. G. Simpson, has queried Bersu's work and largely rehabilitated Collingwood as an excavator.[16]

He also began what was to be the major work of his archaeological career, preparing a corpus of the Roman Inscriptions of Britain, which involved travelling all over Britain to see the inscriptions and draw them; he eventually prepared drawings of nearly 900 inscriptions. It was finally published in 1965 by his student R. P. Wright.

He also published two major archaeological works. The first was The Archaeology of Roman Britain, a handbook in sixteen chapters covering first the archaeological sites (fortresses, towns and temples and portable antiquities) inscriptions, coins, pottery and brooches. Mortimer Wheeler in a review,[17] remarked that "it seemed at first a trifle off beat that he should immerse himself in so much museum-like detail ... but I felt sure that this was incidental to his primary mission to organise his own thinking".

However, his most important work was his contribution to the first volume of the Oxford History of England, Roman Britain and the English Settlements, of which he wrote the major part, Nowell Myres adding the second smaller part on English settlements. The book was in many ways revolutionary for it set out to write the story of Roman Britain from an archaeological rather than a historical viewpoint, putting into practice his own belief in 'Question and Answer' archaeology.

The result was alluring and influential. However, as Ian Richmond wrote, 'The general reader may discover too late that it has one major defect. It does not sufficiently distinguish between objective and subjective and combines both in a subtle and apparently objective presentation'.[18]

The most notorious passage is that on Romano-British art: "the impression that constantly haunts the archaeologist, like a bad smell, is that of an ugliness that plagues the place like a London fog".[19]

Collingwood’s most important contribution to British archaeology was his insistence on Question and Answer archaeology: excavations should not take place unless there is a question to be answered. It is a philosophy which, as Anthony Birley points out,[20] has been incorporated by English Heritage into the conditions for Scheduled Monuments Consent. Still, it has always been surprising that the proponents of the "new" archaeology in the 1960s and the 70s have entirely ignored the work of Collingwood, the one major archaeologist who was also a major professional philosopher. He has been described as an early proponent of archaeological theory.[21]


Author


Outside archaeology and philosophy, he also published the travel book The First Mate's Log of a Voyage to Greece (1940), an account of a yachting voyage in the Mediterranean, in the company of several of his students.

Arthur Ransome was a family friend, and learned to sail in their boat, subsequently teaching his sibling's children to sail. Ransome loosely based the Swallows in Swallows and Amazons series on his sibling's children.


Works



Main works published in his lifetime



Main articles published in his lifetime



Published posthumously


All 'revised' editions comprise the original text plus a new introduction and extensive additional material.


Notes


  1. Collingwood himself used the term historicism, a term that he apparently coined, to describe his approach (for example, in his lecture "Ruskin's Philosophy" lecture, delivered to the Ruskin Centenary Conference Exhibition, Coniston, Cumbria (see Jan van der Dussen, History as a Science: The Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood, Springer, 2012, p. 49)), but some later historiographers describe him as a proponent of "historism" in accordance with the current English meaning of the term (F. R. Ankersmit, Sublime Historical Experience, Stanford University Press, 2005, p. 404).
  2. A translation of the German Historismus first coined by Karl Wilhelm Friedrich Schlegel (see Brian Leiter, Michael Rosen (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Continental Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 2007, p. 175: "[The word 'historicism'] appears as early as the late eighteenth century in the writings of the German romantics, who used it in a neutral sense. In 1797 Friedrich Schlegel used 'historicism' to refer to a philosophy that stresses the importance of history ...").
  3. David Naugle, "R. G. Collingwood and the Hermeneutic Tradition", 1993.
  4. Oxford University Calendar 1913, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1913, pp. 196, 222
  5. Mink, Louis O. (1969). Mind, History, and Dialectic. Indiana University Press, 1.
  6. Collingwood, R. G.; Dray, William H.; van der Dussen, W. J. (1999). The Principles of History and Other Writings in Philosophy of History. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 1. ISBN 978-0-19-823703-7.
  7. D'Oro, Giuseppina; Connelly, James. "Robin George Collingwood". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 3 April 2019.
  8. "historiography – Intellectual history | Britannica". www.britannica.com. Retrieved 18 July 2022.
  9. Collingwood, R. G. (1993). The Idea of History. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 301.
  10. D'Oro, Giuseppina; Connelly, James. "Robin George Collingwood". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 3 April 2019.
  11. Collingwood, R. G.; Dray, William H; van der Dussen, W. J. (1999). The Principles of History and Other Writings in Philosophy of History. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 13. ISBN 978-0-19-823703-7.
  12. Berys Gaut and Dominic McIver Lopes, The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics, Routledge, 2002, ch. 11: "Expressivism: Croce and Collingwood."
  13. R. G. Collingwood (2005). "Man Goes Mad" in The Philosophy of Enchantment. Oxford University Press, 318.
  14. Boucher, David (2003). The Social and Political Thought of R. G. Collingwood. Cambridge University Press. p. 152.
  15. The Vasculum 8:4–9.
  16. Collingwood Studies 5, 1998, 109-119
  17. Antiquity 43
  18. Richmond, I.A., 1944. 'Appreciation of R. G. Collingwood as an archaeologist', Proceedings of the British Academy 29:478
  19. Collingwood, R. G. (Robin George), 1889-1943. (1937). Roman Britain and the English settlements. Myres, J. N. L. (John Nowell Linton) (Second ed.). Oxford: The Clarendon Press. pp. 250. ISBN 019821703X. OCLC 398748 via Internet Archive.
  20. Introductory essay in R. G. Collingwood, An Autobiography, Oxford University Press.
  21. Leach, Stephen (2012). "R.G. Collingwood – An Early Archaeological Theorist?". In Duggan, M.; McIntosh, F.; Rohl, D. J. (eds.). TRAC 2011: Proceedings of the Twenty First Theoretical Roman Archaeology Conference, Newcastle 2011. Theoretical Roman Archaeology Journal. Theoretical Roman Archaeology Conference & Oxbow Books. pp. 10–18. doi:10.16995/TRAC2011_10_18.
  22. Collingwood, R. G. (Robin George) (1916). Religion and Philosophy. Robarts - University of Toronto. London, Macmillan. ISBN 1-85506-317-4 via Internet Archive.
  23. Collingwood, Robin George (1923). Roman Britain. Clarendon Press.
  24. Collingwood, Robin George (1932). Roman Britain. Clarendon Press.
  25. Collingwood, Robin George (1924). Speculum Mentis: Or, The Map of Knowledge. Clarendon Press.
  26. Collingwood, Robin George (1925). Outlines of a philosophy of art. Thoemmes. ISBN 9781855063167.
  27. Collingwood, Robin George (1930). The archaeology of Roman Britain. Methuen & Co. Ltd. ISBN 9780416275803.
  28. Collingwood, Robin George (1933). An essay on philosophical method. The Clarendon Press.
  29. Collingwood, Robin George (1938). The Principles of Art. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-500209-6.
  30. Collingwood, Robin George (1939). An autobiography. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-281247-6.
  31. Collingwood, R. G. (15 April 2003). The First Mates Log. A&C Black. ISBN 9781855063280.
  32. Collingwood, R. G.; Collingwood, Robin George (24 May 2001). An Essay on Metaphysics. Clarendon Press. ISBN 9780199241415.
  33. Collingwood, Robin George (1999). The New Leviathan: Or Man, Society, Civilization, and Barbarism. Clarendon Press. ISBN 9780198238805.
  34. Collingwood, Robin George (31 December 1960). The Idea of Nature. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780198020011.
  35. Collingwood, Robin George (1956). The idea of history. Oxford University Press.
  36. Collingwood, Robin George (1964). Essays in the philosophy of art. Indiana University Press.
  37. Collingwood, Robin George (1965). Essays in the Philosophy of History. University of Texas Press. ISBN 9780292732292.
  38. Collingwood, Robin George; Boucher, David (1989). Essays in Political Philosophy. Clarendon Press. ISBN 9780198248231.
  39. Collingwood, Robin George; Collingwood, R. G. (1999). The Principles of History: And Other Writings in Philosophy of History. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780198237037.
  40. Collingwood, R. G. (2005). The Philosophy of Enchantment: Studies in Folktale, Cultural Criticism, and Anthropology. Oxford University Press.

Sources



Further reading







Текст в блоке "Читать" взят с сайта "Википедия" и доступен по лицензии Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike; в отдельных случаях могут действовать дополнительные условия.

Другой контент может иметь иную лицензию. Перед использованием материалов сайта WikiSort.org внимательно изучите правила лицензирования конкретных элементов наполнения сайта.

2019-2024
WikiSort.org - проект по пересортировке и дополнению контента Википедии